About Indepentarianism

All posts from my blog, the Indepentarian
My books and research articles

Indepentarianism is the political ideology associated with the political theory called “Justice as the Pursuit of Accord” (JPA). I (Karl Widerquist) defined JPA and outlined its theory of freedom in my 2013 book, Independence, Propertyless, and Basic Income: A Theory of Freedom as the Power to Say No. It argues that the promotion of freedom in a society with private property requires, among other things, an unconditional basic income in part, on grounds that it is wrong to put conditions on anyone else’s access to the resources they need to survive. A worker needs the power to say no—not just to any one job, but to all jobs—to enter the market place as a free person and not as a forced laborer. Although this theory is drawn from principles stressing freedom in the most negative sense of the term, it is not associated with theories that use freedom to justify economic inequality. It is committed to the idea that economic and politically disadvantaged people in every society are the least free and that the promotion of freedom in the most meaningful sense requires far greater equality of income, wealth, and political power; greater respect for political dissenters, better stewardship of the environment, and other policies. I am planning to layout the JPA theory of property rights more fully in a future book entitled, Justice as the Pursuit of Accord.

The name, “Justice as the Pursuit of Accord,” comes from the belief that most prevailing theories of justice in political philosophy today are utopian in the sense that they ignore the problem of reasonable disagreement about the basic principles of justice. Social contract theory imagines all the reasonable, rational people in the world agreeing to a hypothetical social contract outlining what justice is. Anyone who doesn’t agree in practice can be dismissed as irrational or unreasonable. Natural rights theorists do not believe that justice comes from any hypothetical agreement. It is just whether anyone agrees or not, but they believe that any rational, reasonable person can discover the true principles of justice by observation and contemplation and anyone who doesn’t agree can be dismissed is irrational or unreasonable. Even the best philosophers are not good at recognizing the difference between reasonable and unreasonable dissent.

These utopian aspects of the leading theories have produced dystopian consequences. Philosophers have misled people into the belief that everyone shares in the benefits of modern society. No matter how disadvantage a person maybe, we are told to believe that they are better off because the government and the property rights system exist. The truth, as Grant S. McCall and I argue in our 2017 book, Prehistoric Myths in Modern Political Philosophy, is that our institutions harm people. Many disadvantaged people are probably worse off than their ancestors were 20,000 years ago.

JPA makes no statement whether there might be a theory of justice to which all rational, reasonable people should or would agree, but it is based on the belief that we are far from the point of discovering such a theory. A true accord exists only if all people are fully autonomous and all literally agree to the social contract or some other basic structure such as a set of natural rights. The essential political problem in the world today is severe disagreement between reasonable people about the most basic principles of justice. We must always pursue that accord, but we should be aware we are unlikely to reach it. Therefore, whoever makes the rules always forces them onto reasonable dissenters. The ruling coalition’s right to make the rules stems both from the agreement of the majority and from their effort to create the minimum negative interference with dissenters. This constraint, of course, requires the governments of the world to treat the disadvantaged and disaffected people of the world much better than they do now—including a payment by those who are most advantage under the existing structure to compensate those who are most disadvantaged under it.

The name, “indepentarianism,” stresses the central role that freedom as independence plays in JPA. The book, Independence, Propertyless, and Basic Income: A Theory of Freedom as the Power to Say No, argues that an individual’s status as a free person is best understood as “Effective Control Self-Ownership” (ECSO freedom, pronounced “exo-freedom” as in external-freedom). In essence: status freedom is the power to say no. An independent person is free from all direct and indirect force to actively serve the interests of others. You can tell a person: go do what you want over there, but if you make it impossible for them to do live as they want without serving some other group of people, you have taken away their status as a free person.

In this sense, most working people in the world are not fully free. If they had direct access to resources, they could hunt, gather, fish, farm, invest, or start a business or start some manufacturing venture by themselves or with whoever wanted to work with them. Instead, the rules of property create “propertylessness,” which in turn indirectly forces the vast majority of people to ask for a job from someone who controls enough resources to give them one. That is, it forces one group of people into become a subordinate of at least one member of another group of people—because we have robbed them of the power to say no to whatever jobs are on offer.

There’s nothing wrong with employment—as long as you choose it freely. Just like there’s nothing wrong with sex—as long as it’s not rape. A choice of bosses without the freedom to say no to all of them is not freedom from forced labor just as a choice of sexual partners without the power to say no to all of them is not freedom from rape.

One of the main reasons I defined indepentarianism as a new ideology is the lack of attention that most of the prevailing political ideologies pay to the injustice of indirectly forced subordination.

The book argues that Universal Basic Income (UBI) is the best way to support ECSO freedom in the modern economy. But UBI support is not synonymous with indepentarianism. Someone could conceivably support indepentarian principles without believing they are best upheld by UBI or a similar policy. Although I hope all UBI supporters will have some interest in indepentarianism, I expect that most of them are not indepentarians. For example, one of the architects of the UBI movement, Philippe Van Parijs, argues for UBI on the theory of justice and/or the ideology he calls “Real Libertarianism,” which is based on very different principles than JPA.

Prehistoric Myths in Modern Political PhilosophyJPA also differs from other political theories in its treatment of property rights in external assets: that is, assets external to the human body including natural resources and the things humans make out of them. Egalitarians tend to assume external assets are naturally collective property. Left-libertarians tend to assume that external assets should naturally owned individually in equal shares. So-called “libertarians” tend to assume external assets are natural unowned, but ownable by the first person to “appropriate” them by some procedure that tends to lead to highly unequal ownership. JPA assumes resources are “naturally” unowned and unownable. The only way to create a truly justice property rights system would be through a property rights accord, which is probably impossible. In the absence of that accord, the ruling coalition is always forcing a system of property onto reasonable dissenters. Therefore, they have to minimize the negative interference that their system of rights imposes on dissenters and future generations. This, responsibility, I argue motivates both a strongly egalitarian and environmentalist property rights system.

I plan to layout JPA property theory more fully in a future book, entitled, Justice as the Pursuit of Accord. It will argue that this responsibility for an egalitarian property rights system requires a UBI high enough not only to maintain ECSO freedom but a UBI set at the highest sustainable level. However, I suspect that not everyone who agrees with the basic principles of indepentarianism will agree with this part of the argument.

I’m very interested in what people think—for and against indepentarianism. I’m especially interested to know whether there are other indepentarians out there. You don’t have to agree with all I’ve said here to call yourself an indepentarian. If you’re in agreement with enough of it to use the term, please say so in a comment. If you’d like to know more about it, please contact me at karl@widerquist.com. I am not interested in creating an echo chamber. I’m interested in respectful dialogue with people taking these ideas in their own directions. I’m also greatly interested in people who criticize any aspect of valetudinarianism.

All posts from my blog, the Indepentarian
My books and research articles

-Karl Widerquist, Begun in New Orleans, completed at Cru Coffee House, Beaufort, North Carolina, May 21, 2017

6 thoughts on “About Indepentarianism

  1. I am an indepentarian. If a person accepts a negative liberty view of freedom, believes that private property if helpful to freedom but recognizes that it is a social construct created by laws, and respects the life choices of dissenters to the social contract, broad agreement with indepentarianism seems a necessary logical conclusion.

  2. Where is the beef?
    In unequal relations you are a possible partner in many transactions. Depending the measure of inequality you are free to say no.
    When you have a basic income, the freedom to say no is bigger then without a UBI. Varoufakis and others have stressed this point. A good reason, a good way to increase equality.
    But not a surprise.

    1. Well, Tom, I have published a book on this theory, and a closely related book, both mentioned in the story. I’ve published several academic articles related to it as well. So, there’s definitely a lot more been than just the stuff in this introduction to the idea. Of course, I don’t expect everyone will have time to read it.

      I”m not sure what you meant by “Depending the measure of inequality you are free to say no.” But you might be getting toward what I think is so important. If you have access to enough resources to meet your basic needs without being anyone’s servant, then you have the power to say no. If you don’t have that access, you do not have the power to say no. You are a forced laborer with a choice of bosses. That’s the not freedom. I’ve found that too much political theory ignores this issue entirely, and that’s why I started trying to lay out Justice as the Pursuit of Accord.

  3. I like the idea of a basic income. I think a basic income and universal healthcare are a good idea in the 21st century. But not on the grounds you have proposed. I don’t think anyone has the right to say no to working and have others pay for it. If a free-market with private ownership is kept in place (and it should be, see USSR for more details), then it will keep those who abstain from work in low enough numbers to work. The basic income should not be a method of allowing those who wish to abstain from tending to their own survival a means to do so. It should be more like a safety net to encourage more people to take risks in the marketplace, who might otherwise not without the basic income to fall back on. From an economic standpoint, this could be closer to revenue-neutral IF it isn’t a free-for-all opt out of working.

    I think it’s also a wonderful delivery vehicle from government playing favorites. If everyone gets a standard amount of assistance, then other government assistance programs can be eliminated. It would no longer matter how much you have or don’t have or what color or gender you are. This is a truly fair and equitable system that works for all. Everyone is giving a level playing field. We can leverage our basic income to work for us, or we can squander it on addictions and meaningless material goods. It truly gives the power back to the individual, without creating a larger government system.

    1. “I don’t think anyone has the right to say no to working and have others pay for it.”

      There are a couple things wrong here: First, basic income is compensation for taking away someone’s right to self-subsist, for restricting their ecso freedom, not a “right to say no to working”. Basic income is just dessert for the loss of freedom, not a reward for being born. No one is “paying for” anything, they’re just no longer allowed to block access to resources, or if they do– they must pay compensation. The result is a basic income as a negative right, not a positive right. This is maybe the most subtle and brilliant point Karl has made on this topic. It’s crucial to understand.

      Second (and I’m not sure if this is really a separate point), you say that one person should not “pay for” others to not work, but why should one group have free access to the labor of another? These “job creators” have to pay their workers, sure, but those workers *must* work for them. So, because they own resources they have a right to have servants? Seems perverse doesn’t it?

Leave a Reply